The Role of Imagination in Constituting Objectivity According to Kant

Document Type : Research Paper

Authors

1 Associate professor of Bu Ali Sina University Iran

2 PhD graduated of Bu Ali Sina University. iran

Abstract

 
 
Received: 01/10/2017       |       Accepted: 016/03/2019
Abstract
Kant believes providing objectivity is one of the most essential functions of imagination. The role of imagination in establishing objectivity includes both the epistemic determinant judgment related to understanding, and the aesthetic reflective judgment. Kant constantly places imagination in connection with matters such as understanding, self-consciousness and/or pure intuition, or common sense, and reflective judgment. Imagination has always maintained a core role in relation to other faculties of cognition. This role could be simply regarded as the possibility of constituting objectivity. This paper seeks, in the first step, to critique pure reason by addressing how imagination in relation with understanding serves as a source of objectivity and then provides answers as to how imagination in its unity with common sense and the operation of reflection presented in the critique of the faculty of judgment, provides an objective reference to them, without which, the common validity for aesthetic-taste judgment will be lost. Hence, in Kant’s view, imagination has a requisite role in providing objectivity.





🞕 salmani, A.,  Haj Rashidian, S. (2019). The Role of Imagination in Constituting Objectivity According to Kant. The Journal of Philosophical - Theological Research, 21(79), 143۔ 164. https://10.22091/jptr-pfk.2019.2502.1744.

Highlights

Introduction

Imagination in Kantian philosophy has an important role. In this essay we try determine the role of imagination. Kant claims the imagination plays essential role in constitution of objectivity. We can find the constitutive role of imagination in the Critique of Pure Reason and the Critique of Judgment. Kant believes providing objectivity is one of the most essential functions of imagination. The role of imagination in establishing objectivity includes both the epistemic determinant judgment, and the aesthetic reflective judgment. Kant constantly places imagination in connection with matters such as understanding, self-consciousness and/or pure intuition, or common sense, and reflective judgment. Imagination has always maintained a central role in relation to other faculties of cognition. This role can be simply considered as the possibility of constituting objectivity.

The role of Imagination in the Critique of Pure Reason

In the Critique of Pure Reason imagination serves understanding and has some essential functions without which objectivity is impossible. The first of these functions is that the imagination produces a transcendental formation which forms a connection between sensation and understanding in order to provide the possibility of applying categories of understanding. However, apart from this function, it is also considered as the origin of every kind of unity. For example, it creates unity in simple perceptions and creates the possibility of the formation of unity in sensory multiplicity; hence it can provide the condition for unity in manifold. Moreover, in relation to pure sensory intuitions, the imagination provides the possibility of their embodiment in time and space as a whole. Similarly, the imagination is the source of the unity of self-consciousness which is necessary for all our cognition. If we look at this collection of functions of imagination we will notice its essential role in the constitution of objectivity.

The role of imagination in the critique of power of judgment

In the critique of power of judgment, Kant doesn’t take imagination to be in service of understanding; rather he regards it in its freedom. Here, imagination makes a connection with understanding as a whole. Although, this relation between them is not a conceptual one, rather, it is a type of harmony which Kant calls “the free game of imagination and understanding”. The free game has an epistemological function and is evaluated in two parts: the analysis of something beautiful and transcendental deduction. In other words, Kant wants to demonstrate the communicability of cognition in human beings through this coordinated game; because if this kind of communicability is not possible, the objectivity of knowledge is impossible as whole. Kant, however, evaluates imagination in relation with pure reflective judgment and the common sense (sensis communis) as well. In this case, imagination first supplies the material for reflective judgment and then discovers “non-subjective others”, in its relation with the common sense. In fact, the reason for the universal validity of taste judgments is the possibility for comparing actual subjective judgment with the possible judgments of these objective others.

Conclusion

The role of imagination in the Critique of Pure Reason is so essential that without taking it into consideration, we cannot achieve any objectivity for the empirical rules gained through understanding and intuition and even experience itself loses its possibility as a judgment. Therefore, one can understand how imagination provides objectivity for judgments related to understanding.

Kant’s main concern in the Critique of Judgment, in which he addresses understanding and imagination in relation to each other, is an epistemological concern which cannot be explained through taste-aesthetic judgment. From this view, taste-aesthetic judgments come under cognitive judgments and Kant tries to provide a cognitive foundation based on the universal communicability of our cognitive faculties for the conformity of judgment with the object. On the other hand, in the transcendental deduction for the aesthetic judgments, Kant has another approach to imagination. In this approach, imagination combines with the act of reflection and sensus communis. By combining with the act of reflection, the imagination provides an represented form of perception which is necessary data for applying reflective judgment. From another aspect, by the eliminating specific condition of the subject and by creating the possibility for the comparison of subjective judgment with the possible judgments of others, the imagination provides the condition for the communicability of taste-aesthetic judgments based on the sensus communis which is in fact, providing the possibility of necessity for it. However, through the sensus communis, the imagination gains access to a non-objective and objective matter that is others. If others were not considered as objective persons that have possible judgments, valid universal communicability, and as a result, the necessity of taste-aesthetic judgments would not be achieved. By what has been discussed so far, it is clear that the function of imagination is essential for the constitution of objectivity in both critiques.

References

-  Allison, H. (2001). Kant’s Theory of Taste. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

-  Allison, H. (1983). Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. London :  Yale University Press.

-  Arendt, H. (1992). Kant’s Political Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

-  Goudeli, K. (2002). Challenges to German Idealism: Schelling, Fichte and Kant Gordonsville, United States. : Springer.

-  Guyer, P. (1997). Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge: the Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge.

-  Guyer, P. (2008). Knowledge, Reason and Taste. New Jersey, United States : Princeton University Press.

-  Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason.Translated and Edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge : The Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge.

References in Arabic / Persian

-  Abdul Karimi, B. (1391 SH). Heidegger va Este‘la (sharhi bar tafsir-i Heidegger az Kant) [Heidegger and the transcendent, an explanation on Heidegger’s commentary by Kant). Qoqnus Publications.

-  Kant, I. (1388 SH). A Critique of Judgment. Translated into Persian as: Naqd-i Quvve-i Hukm (a critique of the faculty of judgment), by: Abdul Karim Rashidian. Ney Publications.

-  Kant, I. (1390 SH). A Critique of Pure Reason. Translated into Persian as: Naqd-i Aql-i Mahz, by: Behrouz Nazari. Bagh-i Ney Publications.

-  Korner, S. (1380 SH). Kant. Translated into Persian as: Falsafa-i Kant (Kant’s philosophy), by: Izzatullah Fuladvand. Khwarazmi Publications.

 

Keywords


 
-  Allison, H. (2001). Kant’s Theory of Taste. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
-  Allison, H. (1983). Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. London :  Yale University Press.
-  Arendt, H. (1992). Kant’s Political Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
-  Goudeli, K. (2002). Challenges to German Idealism: Schelling, Fichte and Kant Gordonsville, United States. : Springer.
-  Guyer, P. (1997). Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge: the Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge.
-  Guyer, P. (2008). Knowledge, Reason and Taste. New Jersey, United States : Princeton University Press.
-  Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason.Translated and Edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge : The Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge.
References in Arabic / Persian
-  Abdul Karimi, B. (1391 SH). Heidegger va Este‘la (sharhi bar tafsir-i Heidegger az Kant) [Heidegger and the transcendent, an explanation on Heidegger’s commentary by Kant). Qoqnus Publications.
-  Hartnack, J. (1387 SH). Kant’s Theory of Knowledge. Translated into Persian as: Nazriye-i Ma‘rifat dar Falsafa-i Kant (the theory of knowledge in Kant’s philosophy), by: Gholam Ali Haddad Adil. Hermes Publications.
-  Helmut Wenzel, C. (1395 SH). An Introduction to Kant's Aesthetics: Core Concepts and Problems. Translated into Persian as: Masa’il va Mafahim-i Kilidi-i Zibai Shenasi-i Kant (core concepts and problems of Kant’s Aesthetics), by: Davud Mirzai & Mania Nourian. Hekmat Publications.
-  Kant, I. (1388 SH). A Critique of Judgment. Translated into Persian as: Naqd-i Quvve-i Hukm (a critique of the faculty of judgment), by: Abdul Karim Rashidian. Ney Publications.
-  Kant, I. (1390 SH). A Critique of Pure Reason. Translated into Persian as: Naqd-i Aql-i Mahz, by: Behrouz Nazari. Bagh-i Ney Publications.
-  Korner, S. (1380 SH). Kant. Translated into Persian as: Falsafa-i Kant (Kant’s philosophy), by: Izzatullah Fuladvand. Khwarazmi Publications.
-  Mahouzi, R. (1394 SH). Kant and the Relation between Imagination and Reason in the Beauty of Art. Journal of Philosophical Investigations. Vol. 9, no. 16, p. 177-196
-  Rogerson, K. (1391 SH). The Problem of Free Harmony in Kant’s Aesthetics. Translated into Persian as: Kant, Hamhangi-i Khiyal va Fahime (Kant: the harmony between imagination and understanding), by: Ali Salamni. Hekmat Publications.
 
CAPTCHA Image