Betz, G. (2013). In Defence of the Value Free Ideal. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 3(2), 207- 220. doi: 10.1007/s13194-012-0062-x.
Biddle, J. (2013). State of the Field: Transient Underdetermination and Values in Science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44(1), 124-133. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2012.09.003.
Churchman, C.W. (1948). Statistics, Pragmatics, and Induction. Philosophy of Science, 15 (3), 249- 268. doi: 10.1086/286991.
Churchman, C.W. (1956). Science and Decision-Making. Philosophy of Science, 23(3), 247-249. doi: 10.1086/287490.
Cranor, F. (1993). Regulating Toxic Substances, A Philosophy of Science and the Law. New York: Oxford University Press.
Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive Risk and Values in Science. Philosophy of Science, 67 (4), 559-579. doi: 10.1086/392855.
Douglas, H. (2009). Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Elliott, K. & Richards, T. (2017). Exploring Inductive Risk: An Introduction. Exploring Inductive Risk, Case Studies of Values in Science. N.p: Oxford University Press.
Franco, p. (2017). Assertion, Non-Epistemic Values, and Scientific Practice. Philosophy of Science, 84(1), 160-80. doi:
10.1086/688939.
Hempel, C.G. (1965). Science and Human Values. Aspects of Scientific Explanation, 81-96. New York: Free Press.
Hudson, R. (2016). Why We Should Not Reject the Value Free Ideal of Science. Perspectives on Science, 24(2), 167- 191. doi: 10.1162/POSC_a_00199.
James, W. (1896). The Will to Believe. The New World, 5, 327- 347.
Jeffrey, R.C. (1956). Valuation and Acceptance of Scientific Hypothesis. Philosophy of Science, 23(3), 237-246. doi: 10.1086/287489.
John, S. (2015). Inductive Risk and the Contexts of Communication. Synthese, 192, 79- 96. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0554-7.
Johnson, D. (1989). Sociological Theory. New York: Wiley and Sons.
Kuhn, T. (1977). Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice. The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Levi, I. (1962). On the Seriousness of Mistakes. Philosophy of Science, 29(1), 47-65. doi: 10.1086/287841.
Longino, H. (1990). Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
McMullin, E. (1983). Values in Science. Philosophy of Science Association. (P. D. Asquith & T. Nickles, Eds.), 2, 3-28.
Mitchell, S.D. (2004). The Prescribed and Proscribed Values in Science Policy. Science, Values and Objectivity. (P. Machamer & G. Wolters, Eds.). University of Pittsburgh Press, 245-255.
Neuman, W.L. (1997). Social Research Methods, Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches. London: Allyn and Bacon.
Reiss, J. & Sprenger, J. (2014). Scientific Objectivity. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Rudner, R. (1953). The Scientist qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments. Philosophy of Science, 20(1), 1-6. doi: 10.1086/287231.
Staley W. (2017). Decisions, Decisions: Inductive Risk and the Higgs Boson. In Elliott, K & Richards, T (Eds.), Exploring Inductive Risk, Case Studies of Values in Science. N.p: Oxford University Press.
Steel, D. (2010). Epistemic Values and the Argument from Inductive Risk. Philosophy of Science, 77(1), 14-34. doi: 10.1086/650206.
Steel, D. (2015). Philosophy and the Precautionary Principle: Science, Evidence, and Environmental Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Steele, K. (2012). The Scientist qua Policy Advisor Makes Value Judgments. Philosophy of Science. 79(5), 893- 904. doi: 10.1086/667842.
Send comment about this article