The Relationship between Scientific Realism and Scientific Progress Accounts

Document Type : Research Paper

Authors

1 Master’s Student, Philosophy of Science Department, Sharif Industrial University, Tehran, Iran.

2 Associate Professor, Philosophy of Science Department, Sharif Industrial University, Tehran, Iran.

Abstract

One of the most significant topics in the philosophy of science literature is the debate between scientific realism and anti-realism. In recent years, a considerable amount of literature has emerged on scientific progress accounts. The aim of this article is to explore the relationship between scientific realism/anti-realism and scientific progress accounts. Scientific realism, in this article, refers to epistemic realism, which posits that mature and successful scientific theories offer an (approximately) true description of the world. In contrast, advocates of epistemic anti-realism reject the possibility of acquiring knowledge about unobservable entities. Scientific progress accounts fall into four categories based on their intended purpose: epistemic, semantic, problem-solving (functional), and noetic. This article argues that the epistemic and semantic accounts, which rely on the concept of truth, are based on scientific realism. The problem-solving account is considered an anti-realistic approach since it replaces the criterion of truth with the ability to solve problems. The primary argument of this article is that although the noetic account appears to use the concept of truth in its explanation, it prioritizes understanding over truth in determining the preferred theory. This means that the criterion for selecting the preferred theory is not approximation to the truth, but rather understanding. As a result, the noetic account is based on an anti-realistic approach.
 
Introduction
The thesis of epistemic realism posits that successful and mature scientific theories are (approximately) true. Also, various accounts of scientific progress focus on specific objectives within science. This article argues that the epistemic and semantic approaches align with a realist perspective, while the problem-solving (functional) and noetic accounts have anti-realist foundations.
Scientific realism
Generally, three theses of scientific realism can be identified: the metaphysical (ontological) thesis, the semantic thesis, and the epistemic thesis. The metaphysical thesis asserts that the world exists independently of the mind. The semantic thesis claims that propositions concerning unobservable entities can be evaluated as true or false implying that all scientific propositions have meaning whether they relate to observable or unobservable entities. The epistemic realism thesis argues that we can acquire knowledge about reality including knowledge about unobservable entities. To be more precise, the claims about theoretical entities in scientific theories are not only meaningful but also provide an almost true depiction of reality.
In this article, realism refers specifically to epistemic realism, which encompasses three main aspects: 1) the existence of a mind-independent world, 2) the attribution of truth or falsity to scientific propositions concerning unobservable entities, and 3) the claim that the propositions in mature scientific theories regarding theoretical entities are nearly true. On the other hand, one advocate of epistemic anti-realism is Bas van Fraassen’s constructive empiricism. According to this perspective, van Fraassen denies the capacity to acquire knowledge about unobservable levels. In this view, the goal of science is not truth but rather empirical adequacy. This means that the objective of scientific endeavor is not to uncover the truth, but rather to construct models that are empirically sufficient.
Scientific progress accounts
Regarding the concept of scientific progress, four accounts have been presented. In the epistemic account, the goal of science is to increase knowledge or justified true belief. Therefore, scientific progress occurs as we accumulate knowledge. In the semantic account, the objective of science is to approach closer to the truth (verisimilitude). This implies that science progresses when our theories are more truth-like. In the problem-solving (functional) approach, the concept of truth is set aside, and the focus shifts to problem-solving or fulfilling specific functions within science. In this account, scientific progress is marked by the development of new theories that effectively solve more problems compared to previous ones. In the new functional approach, scientific progress is defined in terms of the usefulness of the problem-defining and problem-solving. Advocates of the noetic account consider increased understanding to be the goal of science. In other words, science advances when scientists grasp how to correctly explain or predict more aspects of the world.
Scientific progress accounts and scientific realism
In both the epistemic and semantic accounts, truth plays a pivotal role. Justified true belief serves as a necessary condition for acquiring knowledge. In the epistemic account, it is possible to acquire knowledge about theoretical entities. Thus, we can infer that the epistemic account is rooted in scientific realism. In the semantic account, the ultimate aim of science is to achieve complete truth. While achieving complete truth in theories may not be certain within this approach, it is possible to demonstrate their approximate truth. Therefore, according to this account, mature scientific theories are considered to be almost true. Consequently, this account aligns with scientific realism.
In presenting the problem-solving approach, Laudan explicitly argues against truth being the objective of science, as there is no criterion available to gauge the attainment of truth. In other words, if we define the success of scientific theories based on their ability to solve scientific problems, this success does not necessarily indicate the truth of the theory. While mature scientific theories may demonstrate success and possess the capability to solve numerous problems in comparison to earlier theories, this accomplishment does not directly correlate to the truthfulness of the theory. Consequently, this approach adopts an anti-realist perspective towards science.
In the noetic account, priority is given to understanding over approximation to the truth, despite the presence of both criteria. To clarify further, if there are two competing theories, with one being more aligned with reality but the other providing a greater level of understanding, the second theory is considered preferable. Moreover, the concept of the model in the noetic approach resembles the concept of the model in the doctrine of constructive empiricism. This implies that scientific theories do not necessarily provide a true depiction of the world, but rather act as models designed to enhance our understanding. This perspective on scientific theories is anti-realist since it contradicts the thesis of epistemic realism, which asserts that mature scientific theories offer an (almost) true description of the world.
Conclusion
In summary, this article puts forth the following assertions:
l The epistemic and semantic accounts offer explanations for scientific progress within the framework of scientific realism.
l The problem-solving (functional) account takes an anti-realist standpoint by explicitly discarding the notion of truth. Although some argue that the new functional approach can be classified as a realistic perspective, the article contends that it still remains anti-realist.
l The noetic account inherently embraces an anti-realist position. It considers scientific theories as models that prioritize enhancing understanding rather than providing a relatively accurate description of the world.
 

Keywords

Main Subjects


Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth, and logic. Gollancz.
Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs, 41, 64-89.          
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00638.x
Bird, A. (2023). The epistemic approach: scientific progress as the accumulation of knowledge. In Y. Shan (Ed.), New philosophical perspectives on scientific progress (pp. 13-26). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003165859
Boyd, R. N. (1983). On the current status of the issue of scientific realism. In C. G. Hempel, H. Putnam& W. K. Essler (Eds.), Methodology, epistemology, and philosophy of science (pp. 45-90). Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7676-5_3
Cevolani, G., & Tambolo, L. (2013). Progress as approximation to the truth: a defence of the verisimilitudinarian approach. Erkenntnis, 78, 921-935.       
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-012-9362-y
Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: knowing the unobservable. Cambridge University Press.
Chakravartty, A. (2017). Scientific realism. In E. N. Zalta, (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from:       
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/scientific-realism.
Cohen, L. J. (1992). An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford University Press.
Dellsén, F. (2016). Scientific progress: knowledge versus understanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 56, 72-83. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2016.01.003
Dellsén, F. (2017). Understanding without justification or belief. Ratio, 30(3), 239-254.   
https://doi.org/10.1111/rati.12134
Dellsén, F. (2018). Scientific progress: Four accounts. Philosophy Compass, 13, 1-10.     
https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12525
Dellsén, F. (2020). Beyond explanation: understanding as dependency modeling. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71, 1261–1286.     
https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy058
Dellsén, F. (2021). Understanding scientific progress: the noetic account. Synthese, 199(3-4) 11249–11278. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03289-z.
Dellsén, F. (2023). The noetic approach: scientific progress as enabling understanding. In Y. Shan (Ed.), New philosophical perspectives on scientific progress (pp. 62-81). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003165859
Harker, D. (2023). Scientific progress and scientific realism. In Y. Shan (Ed.), New philosophical perspectives on scientific progress (pp. 275-292). Routledge.        
https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003165859
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.
Kukla, A. (1998). Studies in scientific realism. Oxford University Press
Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge University Press.
Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: toward a theory of scientific growth. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Laudan, L. (1981a). A problem-solving approach to scientific progress. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Scientific revolutions (pp. 144-155). Oxford University Press.
Laudan, L. (1981b). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19-49. https://doi.org/10.1086/288975
Massimi, M. (2018). Four kinds of perspectival truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 96, 342-59. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12300
Niiniluoto, I. (1980). Scientific progress. Synthese, 45(3), 427-462.   
https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02221787
Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical scientific realism. Oxford University Press.
Niiniluoto, I. (2019). Scientific progress. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from:  
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/scientific-progress.
Niiniluoto, I. (2023). The semantic approach: scientific progress as increased truthlikeness. In Y. Shan (Ed.), New philosophical perspectives on scientific progress (pp. 62-81). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003165859.
Park, S. (2017). Does scientific progress consist in increasing knowledge? Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48, 569–579. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9363-2
Park, S. (2022). Scientific realism and scientific progress. In S. Park (Ed.), Embracing scientific realism (pp. 155-176). Springer.
Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach. Clarendon Press.
Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: how science tracks truth. Routledge.
Rowbottom, D. P. (2008). N-rays and the semantic view of scientific progress. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 277-278. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2008.03.010
Rowbottom, D. P. (2010). What scientific progress is not: against Bird’s epistemic view. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24(3), 241-255.   
https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2010.522407
Shan, Y. (2019). A new functional approach to scientific progress. Philosophy of Science, 86, 739–758. https://doi.org/10.1086/704980
Shan, Y. (2020). A functional account of the progress. In Y. Shan (Ed.), Doing integrated history and philosophy of science: a case study of the origin of genetics (pp. 101-117). Springer.
Shan, Y. (2023). The functional approach: scientific progress as increased. In Y. Shan (Ed.), New philosophical perspectives on scientific progress (pp. 46-61). Routledge.    
https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003165859
Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford University Press.
Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Clarendon.
CAPTCHA Image