On the Logic of Permissiveness of Belief

Document Type : Research Paper

Author

Abstract

According to the theory of normativity of belief, understanding the idea that there is a normative relationship between the mental act of believing and the content of belief reinforces the concept of propositional attitude of belief. The issue of how to formulate the aforementioned normative relationship- which can also be called the issue of norm-based formulation, for short-is the one which is abundantly studied in relevant philosophical literature. In the philosophical literature of two or three recent years, two kinds of norm-based formulation are proposed. First, correctness of a proposition is the necessary condition for the permissiveness of the belief in that proposition; second, correctness of a proposition is the necessary and sufficient condition for the permissiveness of the belief in that proposition. Providing a brief account of the theory of normativity of belief and reviewing older norm-based formulations, the present paper argues for the first view and against the second one.
Seyyed Ali Kalantari[1]


[1] . Assistant professor of philosophy department, Isfahan University 

Keywords


  •  

    • § Boghossian, P. (2003). "The Normativity of Content", in: Philosophical Issues, 13: 31–45.
    • § Boghossian, P. (2005). "Is Meaning Normative?" in: Philosophy Science Scientific Philosophy, ed. A. Beckermann and C. Nimtz, Paderborn: Mentis.
    • § Bykvits, K. and A. Hattiangadi (2007). "Does Thought Imply Ought?" in: Analysis 67: 277-85.
    • § Engel, P. (2001). "Is truth a norm?" in: Interpreting Davidson, eds. P. Kotatko et al. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
    • § Gibbard, A. (2003). "Thoughts and Norms" in: Philosophical Issues, 13: 83–98.
    • § Gibbard, A. (2005). "Truth and Correct Belief" in: Philosophical Issues, 15: 338–350.
    • § Gluer, K. and Wikforss, A. (2009). "Against Content Normativity" in: Mind, 118: 31–70.
    • § Gluer, K. and Wikforss, A. (2010). "The Truth Norm and Guidance: A Reply to Steglich-Petersen", in: Mind, 119: 757-761.
    • § Gluer, k. and Wikforss, A. (forthcoming): "Against Belief Normativity", in: Timothy Chan (ed.), The Aim of Belief, Oxford University Press.
    • § Kalantari, S. A. and Luntley, M. (2013). "On the Logic of Aiming at Truth", in: Analysis, 73: 419-422.
    • § Raleigh, T. (2013). 'Belief Norms and Blindspots", in: Southern Journal of Philosophy, 51: 243-269.
    • § Shah, N. (2003). "How Truth Governs Belief", in: Philosophical Review, 112: 447-482.
    • § Shah, N. (2006). "A New Argument for Evidentialism", in: Philosophical Quarterly, 56: 481-498.
    • § Shah, N. and Velleman, D. (2005). "Doxastic Deliberation", in: Philosophical Review, 114: 497-534.
    • § Steglich-Petersen, A. (2006). "No Norm Needed: On the Aim of Belief", in: Philosophical Quarterly, 56: 499–516
    • § Steglich-Petersen, A. (2009). "Weighing the Aim of Belief", in: Philosophical Studies, 145: 395-405.
    • § Vahid, H. (2006). "Aiming at Truth: Doxastic Vs. Epistemic Goals", in: Philosophical Studies, 131: 303-335.
    • § Vellman, D. (2000). The Possibility of Practical Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • § Wedgwood, R. (2002). "The Aim of Belief", in: Philosophical Perspectives, 16: 276–297.
    • § Whiting, D. (2010). "Should I believe the truth?" in: Dialectica, 64: 213–24.
    • § Whiting, D. (2013). "Truth: the Aim and Norm of Belief", [In Special Issue: The Aim of Belief], Teorema 32, (3).
    • § Williams, B. (1973). "Deciding to Believe", In his Problems of the Self, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
CAPTCHA Image