Free Will versus Determinism - As Determined by Radical Conceptual Changes

نوع مقاله : مقاله علمی پژوهشی

نویسنده

Senior Professor of Christian Philosophy, Fuller Theological Seminary, Pasadena, CA, USA.

چکیده

My objective in this article is to question whether the problem of free will can, within our current conceptual system, be framed coherently. It is already widely recognized that a mental faculty, the will, needed to initiate action, no longer fits with current thought. However, we can still ask whether human decisions and actions are determined by something other than the agent. So the important question is whether we still have a cogent concept of determinism. The two prevalent alternatives are a closed set of deterministic laws of nature, and a simple distillation of the principle of sufficient reason: all events must have a cause. I first provide examples showing that philosophical concepts come and go as categorial frameworks change. The modern concept of deterministic laws of nature was developed during the latter half of the modern period and is now being called seriously into question. G. W. Leibniz’s principle of sufficient reason could only be justified in theological terms, which most contemporary Western scholars reject. I end with an inadequate account of a dawning worldview based on complex adaptive systems theory, in which most human actions are best described in terms of non-necessitating propensities.

کلیدواژه‌ها


عنوان مقاله [English]

Free Will versus Determinism - As Determined by Radical Conceptual Changes

نویسنده [English]

  • Nancey Murphy
Senior Professor of Christian Philosophy, Fuller Theological Seminary, Pasadena, CA, USA.
چکیده [English]

My objective in this article is to question whether the problem of free will can, within our current conceptual system, be framed coherently. It is already widely recognized that a mental faculty, the will, needed to initiate action, no longer fits with current thought. However, we can still ask whether human decisions and actions are determined by something other than the agent. So the important question is whether we still have a cogent concept of determinism. The two prevalent alternatives are a closed set of deterministic laws of nature, and a simple distillation of the principle of sufficient reason: all events must have a cause. I first provide examples showing that philosophical concepts come and go as categorial frameworks change. The modern concept of deterministic laws of nature was developed during the latter half of the modern period and is now being called seriously into question. G. W. Leibniz’s principle of sufficient reason could only be justified in theological terms, which most contemporary Western scholars reject. I end with an inadequate account of a dawning worldview based on complex adaptive systems theory, in which most human actions are best described in terms of non-necessitating propensities.

کلیدواژه‌ها [English]

  • Categorial frameworks
  • Complex systems
  • Determinism
  • Free will
  • Historicist philosophy
  • Laws of nature
Audi, R. (Ed.) (1995). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University.
Augustine of Hippo. (391-395 CE). De Libero Arbitrio, books 2 and 3.
Bechtel, W. & Richardson, R. C. ([1993] 2010). Discovering Complexity. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Bishop, R. C. (2002). Chaos, Indeterminacy, and Free Will. In Robert Kane(Ed.), Oxford Handbook of Free Will, (pp.111-124). Oxford, UK: Oxford University.
Borarradori, G. (1994). The American Philosopher: Conversations with Quine, Davidson, Putnam, Nozick, Danto, Rorty, Cavell, MacIntyre, and Kuhn. Crocillo, R. (Trans.). Chicago & London: University of Chicago.
Butterfield, J. (1998). Determinism. In William Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (vol.3, pp.33-39). London and New York: Routledge.
Cartwright, N. (1999). The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Cary, P. (2000). Augustine’s Invention of the Inner Self: The Legacy of a Christian Platonist. New York: Oxford University Press.
Craig, E. (Ed.). (1998). The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (10 Vols.), London and New York: Routledge. doi: 10.4324/9780415249126-L109-1.
Dihle, A. (1982). The Theory of the Will in Classical Antiquity. Berkeley, CA: University of California.
Feyerabend, P. K. (1975). Against Method (1st ed.). London: New Left Books.
Garber, D. (1998). Leibniz. In William Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (vol.5, pp.541-562). London and New York: Routledge
Golshani, M. (2020). Science Needs a Comprehensive Worldview. Theology and Science, 18(3), pp.438-447.
Gutting, G. (Ed.). (1980). Paradigms & Revolutions: Applications and Appraisals of Thomas Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame.
Heylighen, F. (2010). Self-organization of Complex, Intelligent Systems:
The ECCO Paradigm for Transdisciplinary Integration. Presented at Symposium for research across borders, Luxembourg (Unpublished).
Irwin, T. H. (1992). Who Discovered the Will? Berkeley, CA: University of California. Available at: https.//www.jstore.org/132.174.251.161.
Juarrero, A. (1999). Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior as a Complex System. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Kane, R. (Ed). (2002a). The Oxford Handbook of Free Will. Oxford, UK: Oxford University.
Kane, R. (2002b). Introduction. In Robert Kane(Ed.). Oxford Handbook of Free will. (pp.3-41). Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Kuhn, T. S. ([1962] 1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. (2nd enlarged ed.) Chicago: University of Chicago.
Körner, S. (1970). Categorial Frameworks. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Leibniz, G. W. ([1668/1686] 1846). Discourse de Métaphysique. Available at: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2707429.
Leibniz, G. W. (1710). Essais de Théodicée sur la Bonté de Dieu, la Liberté de L’homme et L’origine Du Mal. Amsterdam: Troyel.
Leslie, J. (1989). Universes. London: Routledge.
MacIntyre, A. C. (1966). A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame.
MacIntyre, A. C. (1977). Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science. Monist 60 (pp.453-72). Reprint in Gutting (1980, pp.54-74).
MacIntyre, A. C. (1994). Nietzsche or Aristotle? In Giovanna Borradori & Rosanna Crocillo
(Eds.), The American Philosopher: Conversations with Quine, Davidson, Putnam, Nozick, Danto, Rorty, Cavell, MacIntyre, Kuhn, (pp.137-152). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago.
Mason, R. (2000). Before Logic. New York: State University of New York Press.
Matson, W. I. (1987). A New History of Philosophy: Ancient & Medieval. (vol.2) San Diego, CA: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Murphy, N. (1996). Beyond Liberalism and Fundamentalism: How Modern and Postmodern Philosophy Set the Theological Agenda. Valley Forge, PA: Trinity Press International.
Popper, K. R. (1990). A World of Propensities. Bristol, UK: Thoemmes.
Prigogine, I. (1996). The End of Certainty: Time, Chaos, and the New Laws of Nature. (In: collaboration with Stengers, I.) New York: Free Press.
Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago.
Sapire, D. (1995). Propensity. In Robert Audi (Ed.), Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. (p.751). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University.
Scott, A. (2004). The Development of Nonlinear Science. Revista del Nuovo Cimento, 27(10-11), 1-115.
Sobel, J. H. (1998). Puzzles for the Will. Toronto: University of Toronto.
Spinoza, B. (1677). Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata. Cited in Mason (1987), p. x.
Strawson, G. (2002). The Bounds of Freedom. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (pp.441-460). Oxford University Press.
Van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and Symmetry. New York: Oxford University.
Wittgenstein, L. ([1953] 2009). Philosophical Investigations. (Rev. 4th Ed., G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker & J. Schulte, Trans.; Hacker & Schulte, Eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.
CAPTCHA Image